Science/Religion [also available in Adobe Acrobat format]
(A talk given at King Edward VI Camp Hill School, Birmingham, March 2002)
Science and Religion. First, there
is no such thing as Science - but there are many sciences investigating different
parts and aspects of the universe. (I am restricting attention here to the physical
sciences as distinguished from psychology and the social sciences.) All of these
are legitimate, valuable, fascinating, indispensable, worthy of a lifetime's
efforts. None of them is in itself either pro- or anti-religion.
However there is a philosophy which a large majority of those working in the
physical sciences today take for granted. This was once called materialism.
But that is not a good word for it because of its association with materialism
in the sense of being materialistic, concerned only with material possessions
rather than moral and cultural values, and there is no reason why those who
hold this philosophy should be any more materialistic in that sense than anyone
else. The accepted terms today are 'naturalism' and 'physicalism', meaning the
belief that the physical universe constitutes the totality of reality. On this
view there is nothing beyond the physical, no trans- or meta- or supra-physical
or suprasensory reality such as the religions affirm. And so the entirety of
reality is, at least in principle, fully describable and understandable by the
empirical sciences. This is so widely taken for granted today that it is often
equated with Science or with the scientific point of view. But I am going to
argue that on the contrary naturalism is not 'scientific truth' but a philosophy
which most but by no means all scientists hold; and that it is, when ardently
believed, or unquestioningly taken for granted, a faith position - as much so
as religious faith.
To show this in short space I want to concentrate on the fact that the physical
universe includes human bodies, and thus human brains, these being the particular
bits of the physical universe that I want to focus on. Here naturalism, or physicalism,
is so fully taken for granted today that, for example, the excellent account
of the brain by Rita Carter (advised by Professor Christopher Frith) is not
called Mapping the Brain but Mapping the Mind. However I shall argue that at
this point physicalism becomes self-contradictory, so that the physicalist has
to retreat - or rather, I would say, has to advance - to a more open position
which accepts that there may possibly be suprasensory realities such as the
religions speak of.
But first let me clarify. Surely, you may say, any physical scientist would
grant that consciousness and thought exist and that these are not physical objects.
Consciousness may be ephemeral, its contents in constant flux, with thoughts
coming and going all the time, but consciousness does exist. This is of course
not in dispute. But the question is, What is it's status? Different schools
of physicalist thought have given different answers, which however boil down
to two main options.
One is mind/brain identity. This is the view that thought is, purely and simply,
the functioning of the brain. Consciousness is neural activity, consisting without
remainder in the electro-chemical activity in the brain. Thus a particular episode
of conscious thinking, and the specific electro-chemical processes which are
taking place in the brain at the same time, are not distinguishable as physical
and non-physical but are one and the same physical event.
However this mind/brain identity theory, also known as central-state materialism,
is not nearly so widely held today as it was a decade or two ago. It's basic
problem is a very obvious one. Suppose a neuro-surgeon has exposed a patient's
brain and, with the aid of instruments registering its electrical activity,
is tracing the successive co-ordinated firings of the neurons. The patient is
conscious, there being no pain nerves in the brain, and she reports what is
going on in her mind, the contents of her consciousness. Suppose she is deliberately
visualizing a mountain scene with a blue lake in the foreground and pine trees
beyond it growing in a green swathe up the lower slopes of a mountain range.
Does it really make sense to say that the electro-chemical activity that the
surgeon is monitoring with his instruments, taking place in the gray matter
that he can see and touch, literally is that visualized mountain scene which
forms the content of the patient's consciousness? It makes sense - whether or
not it is true - to say that the brain activity causes the conscious experience.
It makes sense - again, whether or not it is true - to say that there could
be no conscious experience without that brain activity. But does it make sense
to say that the brain activity actually is, identically, that visualized scene
occupying the patient's consciousness? That is strongly counter-intuitive, even
to the point of being unintelligible.
However this appeal to ordinary experience is dismissed by some neuroscientists
as 'folk-psychology'. But that is pejorative spin language. Whilst there is
an overwhelming body of evidence for full consciousness/brain correlation, to
suppose that any accumulation of this evidence, however great, constitutes evidence
for their identity is a simple logical fallacy. Neural activity in my skull,
and my conscious mental act of formulating the sentence that I am now uttering,
are completely correlated with one another, so that in knowing one it is possible,
ideally and in principle, to infer the other. But it does not follow that my
conscious subjective mental activity literally is an event in the neurons, synapses
and electric charges in my head. That A and B exist in full correlation with
each other does not mean that they are identical.
We can summarize thus far by saying
that there is no pain in the brain but there is in consciousness. And likewise
the range of colours that we see and sounds that we hear and sensations that
we feel do not exist in the brain but do exist in our consciousness.
So naturalistic neuroscientists have generally moved to the theory that consciousness
is a new emergent feature or aspect of brain activity, an aspect that develops
when the brain reaches a certain degree of complexity. It is an epiphenomenon
of brain activity, existing only whilst the brain is working. It is totally
dependent upon brain function although not actually identical with it, and it
has no causal power over the brain. As an analogy, you can think of the way
in which an electric current flowing through a light bulb produces light, but
as soon as you switch off the electricity there ceases to be any light. As the
light in the bulb is not identical with the electricity in the bulb, but is
a temporary product of its operation, so consciousness is not identical with
the brain but is a temporary product of its operation.
However the data that we have to go on seem to be more complicated than either
mind/brain identity or consciousness as an epiphenomenon of brain activity.
On the face of it our continuous daily experience is evidence of a two way causation,
states of the brain producing states of consciousness, and conscious decisions
producing states of the brain which in turn cause bodily behavior.
On the one hand it is a matter of common observation that various drugs change
the chemistry of the brain and nervous system, thereby affecting mental life.
General anaesthesia causes unconsciousness; alcohol can lower inhibitions and
make it unsafe to drive by impairing judgment and releasing aggression; valium
can calm stress and anxiety; cannabis can produce a temporary sense of well-being;
and the hard drugs can cause hallucinations and all sorts of other extraordinary
and sometimes dangerous effects.
And the tremendous and continuing
advances in mapping the functions of the different areas of the brain now go
far, far beyond these common observations, to a mapping of the different functions
of different parts of the brain. But at the same time the neurophysiologists
emphasize that the brain functions as a living whole, although within its total
activity different areas specialize in different tasks. And they add that far
more is still unknown than is known about the brain.
To take a short cut straight to the
relevance of all this to religion, some neuro-scientists claim to have located
an area in the temporal lobe that produces what they describe as religious experiences.
Thus one researcher (Dr Michael Persinger) reports that by stimulating this
area, 'Typically people report a presence. One time we had a strobe light going
and this individual actually saw Christ in the strobe. [Another] experienced
God visiting her. Afterwards we looked at her EEG and there was this classic
spike and slow-wave seizure over the temporal lobe at the precise time of the
experience' . I'm going to say more about religion later. But let me just say
at this point that neuroscientists often have extremely naïve ideas about
religion and assume that a bright light, or seeing a vision of a religious figure
- whose assumed identity depends on the patient's cultural background, - or
feeling at one with the environment, is necessarily a religious experience.
When, for example, a certain lesion which disconnects one part of the brain
from another can cause a patient to think that he is God, invulnerable to human
powers, or when other lesions produce other extraordinary experiences which
are structured by religious concepts, they readily assume that religious experience
is in general hallucinatory. But within the great religious traditions themselves
there is a more sophisticated attitude to 'mystical' experiences. If you read
the great Christian mystics, for instance, you find that they were acutely aware
that not all religious visions, auditions, photisms, etc are religiously authentic.
Teresa of Avila, for example, as a medieval person, expressed this suspicion
as a belief that the devil can cause such experiences . And the criterion for
authenticity, in addition to the tradition-specific test of the orthodoxy of
the messages received, was always the fruits of the experience in the life of
the mystic. If it made him or her a manifestly better person, it was genuine;
if not, not. And this is the main criterion across all the great traditions.
So the possibility of inducing by
drugs or surgical interventions in the brain, visions, auditions, etc that are
religious in the sense that they are formed by religious images and concepts,
does not show that mystical awareness in general is delusory. A mind dominated
by the naturalistic assumption automatically jumps to that conclusion, but it
is not a valid inference. In the light of modern neuroscience we should confidently
expect there to be states of the brain correlated with awareness of the Transcendent.
This is no more surprising than in the case of our awareness of everything else.
And likewise it should not be surprising that there can be false perceptions
in religious-seeming awareness as there can in ordinary awareness. A blow on
the head may make you see stars which are not physically there, and various
drugs can induce much more complex hallucinations, but this does not show that
there is no physical world that can also be perceived more or less correctly.
Nor does the fact that some drugs can produce religious-seeming hallucinations
show that there is no transcendent reality of which there may also be genuine
forms of awareness.
So in short, there is massive evidence
of altered brain states causing altered states of consciousness. But on the
other hand it is equally a matter of first-hand observation that we can consciously
decide to move our finger or to utter certain words, and it is prima face evident
that this mental volition produces brain activity which causes the moving of
the finger or the production of the words; and again it is prima facie evident
that we can consciously imagine a certain scene or consider an argument or a
theory and freely make judgments about it - indeed this is what we are all doing,
or at least think that we are doing, at the present moment. Thus it is prima
face evident that when we exercise our free will in mental or physical action
the state of the brain is correspondingly altered.
This brings us to the internal contradiction
within the naturalistic assumption as it shows in the brain/consciousness relationship.
The sciences proceed on the basis that the physical world functions always and
everywhere in accordance with the regularities and patterns that we call the
laws of nature. And universal law entails universal causation. In other words,
events do not occur at random but are always caused to happen, and the causation
is always law governed.
There is however a complication to this picture in the principle of indeterminacy or uncertainty in the behavior of the most fundamental particles. According to quantum mechanics, at the minutest subatomic level it is in principle impossible to measure precisely both position and velocity at the same time. There is thus an element of uncertainty or unpredictability at the heart of nature. It seems clear, however, that this micro indeterminacy so to speak cancels out at the macro level of objects consisting of trillions of sub-atomic particles. It does not create an indeterminacy in the world of humanly observable physical objects and processes.
However I am not going to insist
on this here because it does not in the end affect either way the question of
human free will, which is the issue towards which we are moving. For we are
no more free if our thoughts and actions are randomly determined than if they
are rigidly determined. Either way they are not freely determined by us. Given
either strict determinism, or an indeterminacy due to subatomic unpredictability,
human freewill would be excluded.
So we come now to the basic issue
that has been hovering all the time in the background, the question of intellectual
freedom and determinism. This is seldom discussed by neuroscientists. Rita Carter,
however, expounding what she takes to be the outcome of their work, says, 'some
illusions are programmed so firmly into our brains that the mere knowledge that
they are false does not stop us from seeing them. Free will is one such illusion.
. . [But] Future generations will take for granted that we are programmable
machines just as we take for granted the fact that the earth is round' . What
she has not noticed however is that she is tacitly exempting her own thought
processes from the scope of her dogma. But if we apply her conclusion to her
own thought processes in coming to that conclusion, its status is dramatically
altered.
The point was forcefully made by
the great philosopher of science Karl Popper . But it goes back to Epicurus,
who said, 'He who says that all things happen of necessity cannot criticize
another who says that not all things happen of necessity. For he has to admit
that the assertion also happens of necessity'.
This seems to me to be basically right, although it needs to be developed a
bit further. Let me put it in my own way.
Let us suppose that the physical world is completely determined, at least at
the macro level which includes our bodies and of course our brains. And suppose
that, as will then be the case, some of us are causally determined in such a
way that we believe that complete determinism obtains whilst others are causally
determined in such a way that we believe the contrary. The question is whether
those who are right in believing that they are totally determined can properly
be said to know that they are right, or whether on the contrary if they are
right they can never properly be said to know or rationally believe this, or
indeed anything else?
To get at this question, suppose
there is a non-determined observer watching our totally determined world from
outside it. This observer is able to think freely, to direct her attention at
will, to weigh up evidence and consider reasons, and out of all this to form
her own judgments. She can see that our world is a completely determined system
and that everyone in it is completely determined in all their actions, thoughts,
imaginings, feelings, emotions, day dreamings, visualizings, and all their reasoning,
judging and believing. But whilst this undetermined observer knows that we earthlings
are all completely determined she knows it in a sense of 'know' in which even
those earthlings who correctly believe it nevertheless do not know it. I am
not here invoking an ideal sense of 'know' in which it turns out that we can
only be said to know tautologies, but am using the term in the everyday sense
of knowledge as well-based rational belief. Thus if there is or could be free
will including, crucially, non-determined intellectual volitions, a free being
can come rationally to hold beliefs in a sense in which a totally determined
being never can. Let us for convenience call the free being's knowledge knowledge
A and the determined being's knowledge B, and speak of them as functioning respectively
in mode A and mode B.
Given this terminology, I suggest
that those who believe that a total determinism obtains, and who of course believe
that they are right in so believing, are in the impossible position of implicitly
professing to function in mode A when, if they are right, they must in fact
be functioning in mode B, the determined mode. This, I suggest, is a self-refuting
position in the existential sense incurred, for example, by someone who says,
'I do not exist'; for in order for anyone to assert that he does not exist,
what he asserts must be false. Likewise, to assert in mode A - that is, as an
evidence and reason based judgment, - that all judgments including this one
can only be made in the physically determined mode B, is to be in a state of
existential self-contradiction.
In other words, the argument between the determinist and the non-determinist can only take place in what both assume to be mode A. But whereas the non-determinist believes that what they are both assuming is true, the determinist believes that it is false, and is thus claiming to know in mode A that there is no mode A.
This is the self-contradiction at
the heart of physicalism.
However an escape route from this
intellectually intolerable position has been suggested. A computer can be programmed
to go through an accurate deductive process and reach the correct conclusion.
And what could be more rational than the logical process pursued by a computer?
May not our brains be biological computers able to function in this way? This
is in effect what the determinist believes to be going on in the discussions
about determinism. We are totally determined, but the determinist may nevertheless
be determined in such a way that he arrives at a true conclusion, just as a
computer may.
The right response to this is, I
think, that Yes we may be totally determined, in which case the determinist
is determined in such a way that what he believes is true. But if so, none of
us can ever know or rationally believe that this is the case. Two people debating
the question would be like two computers purring away in accordance with their
different programs, with only an outside observer operating in mode A being
able to tell which is and which is not programmed to arrive at the truth. In
the case of computers, the mode A outside observer is the programmer, who has
to know what sound reasoning is in order to program a computer to reach it.
Or of course if the computer is built and programmed by a prior computer, the
mode A observer is the non-determined programmer of that computer; and so on
in as long a regress as you like. And likewise with ourselves considered as
fully determined computers. If anyone is to know what is true and what is false
among the conclusions which differently programmed human computers reach, that
cannot be any of us in mode B but could only be a non-determined mode A programmer.
But now another suggestion offers
itself. Perhaps the ultimate programmer is nature itself. For true beliefs aid
survival. May not the evolutionary pressures of the environment gradually eliminate
poorly programmed brains whilst rewarding correctly programmed ones, thus moving
the whole development in a truth finding direction? On this theory there is
no mode A consciousness, but nevertheless the whole process whereby our brains
have become as efficient as they are is a purely natural phenomenon.
But problems at once arise. The most
fundamental one is that if this theory is true we could never know or believe
this in mode A, since all believing would be in mode B. But further, why would
a truth-seeking machine arrive at the species-wide delusion that it is not determined?
Presumably because the delusion has survival value. But how could a deluded
consciousness possibly have survival value if we are simply totally determined
bio-computers? Being determined, we do what we are caused to do, and consciousness,
whether deluded or not, adds nothing. Against this, it could be said that biological
evolution, in its continual experimentation, has sometimes produced non-functional
by-products, and perhaps consciousness, with its sense of mental freedom, is
one of these. But this 'perhaps' is dwarfed by a massive 'perhaps not', for
generally the evolutionary process has aided efficient function, and unless
there are positive reasons to the contrary the presumption must lie with this.
And so it seems to me that in affirming
the freedom of his or her own reasoning faculty the naturalist must move to
a more open point of view. If our mental life is not purely electro-chemical
neural activity, it follows that there is non-physical as well as physical reality.
It further follows that this non-physical reality is not a mere epiphenomenon
of matter but is able to exert causal power upon one part of the material universe,
namely the human brain. A door has thus opened to the possibility that the human
person is more than a purely physical organism, and also that there may be a
suprasensory reality such as the religions point to, and a non-determined capacity
of our own nature to respond to it. A door of possibility has opened. The naturalist
may resolutely refuse to go through that door, or may simply turn her back on
it and ignore it, but nevertheless the door stands open.
So what I have been arguing - and
this is my main contribution today to your science/religion discussions - is
that the naturalistic assumption that the totality of reality consists of physical
matter and that there is therefore no suprasensory reality is not a defensible
position.
What may lie on the other side of
that open door? Both religious believers and non-believers usually think of
religion only in terms of the religious tradition with which they are familiar,
which is the one into which we were born and by which we have been formed. But
this is too narrow a focus. The central feature of religion in virtually all
its forms, both theistic and non-theistic, is the belief in a reality that transcends
the physical universe but is accessible to the spiritual aspect of our own human
nature, the aspect that is spoken about in various ways, such as the image of
God within us, or the atman, or the universal Buddha nature. For our present
purpose I am going to call that reality simply the Transcendent or the Real.
I am using this because our more familiar word 'God' can so easily bring with
it connotations which I want to avoid. It is often taken to mean an infinitely
powerful Being who sometimes intervenes miraculously on earth in response to
human prayers, as is of course described at many points in the Bible - as one
obvious example, making the sun stand still for twenty-four hours so that the
Israelites could have longer to slay their opponents. But if there were an all-powerful
intervening Being like that, I wouldn't think him (or her) worthy of worship.
That's for a very simple reason. Suppose there's a car crash in the road outside
and three of the people in it are killed but one survives more or less unhurt.
If that one, believing in a miraculously intervening deity, then thanks God
for saving her life, she's forgetting that if God decided to save her, he must
have decided at the same time not to save the other three. But if he could if
he wanted equally easily save everyone from all harm, why is there so much pain
and suffering in the world? This would be a cruelly arbitrary God, and the only
people who could reasonably worship him would be the chosen few whom he protects.
Focussing, then, not on God in that
sense but upon what I shall call the ultimate transcendent reality, or the Transcendent
for short, to which the religions are our range of human responses, why believe
that there is any such reality?
Here we have to distinguish between
what we can call first-hand and second-hand religion. Believers at second-hand
include the multitudes within each tradition who simply believe what they have
been brought up to believe, so that if they had happened to have been born in
another part of the world they would instead have believed what people there
are brought up to believe - though the believer at second-hand may sometimes
nevertheless have a genuine and lively faith derived from the much greater spiritual
figures whose religion is first-hand, based on their own experience. The greatest
of these are the founding figures of the various religious traditions - in historical
order, the Upanishadic sages, the Buddha, Lao-Tze (or whoever wrote the Tao
Te Ching), Moses and the other great Hebrew prophets, Jesus, St Paul, Muhammad,
Guru Nanak, and so on, and then the saints or mahatmas ('great souls') who have
renewed or reformed the traditions, and also in varying degrees innumerable
more ordinary believers who participate at least sometimes and to some extent
in first-hand religious experience.
Naturalistic thinkers often assume
that religious belief arises as an attempt to explain the world - thunder storms
are due to the anger of the gods, for example, - or by an inference from the
world to God, the order of the world or the 'fine-tuning' of cosmic evolution,
for example, being taken as proof of a creator. But none of this is the real
basis of religious faith. The most basic way in which we know that anything
exists is not as an inference from evidence but by that which exists impacting
us, in other words by our experiencing it. When I hold up my hand and look at
it I don't infer that there is a hand there, I see the hand. As David Hume showed
long ago, we don't believe in the world around us on the basis of an argument
from there seeming to be a world to the conclusion that there is a world. And
this is just as well, because no such argument would be valid. You can't in
fact prove that anything exists outside your own consciousness. What we all
do is simply trust our experience. We are all first-hand believers in the existence
of a world beyond our own minds. If we didn't trust our experience of seeing
a brick wall, or an oncoming bus that will run us over if we don't jump out
of its way, the world would soon eliminate us. It is the nature of rationality
to trust our experience, except when we have a specific reason to think that
an apparent perception is really an hallucination. So our material environment
forces itself upon our attention. We trust our experience on pain of death.
Now the material world, in itself,
is value-free. It is just 'brute fact', and whilst it determines our range of
possible actions, to be forced to be aware of it does not undermine our inner
moral and spiritual freedom within the given physical world. But suppose that
as well as living in this physical environment we also at the same time live
within a non-physical supranatural environment which does not force itself upon
us, but awareness of which is a free response made possible by the spiritual
aspect of our nature. It does not force itself upon us because to become aware
of it involves a shift from natural self-centeredness to a new centring in the
Transcendent, beginning to liberate within us our capacity for unrestricted
love and compassion, and this is a shift or a transformation which can only
be entered upon freely. By its very nature it cannot be forced, as can awareness
of the value-free material world.
But there is another obvious difference
between sense experience and religious experience, namely that whereas all human
beings perceive the physical world, and perceive it in (almost) the same way,
religious experience is not universal and when it occurs it takes a wide variety
of different forms within the different traditions that have developed. How
can this be? The answer lies in a principle, known to today as critical realism,
the view that there is a reality outside us but that we can only know it in
the ways that our own cognitive equipment and conceptual systems make possible.
It is the principle that Thomas Aquinas stated long ago when he said that 'Things
known are in the knower according to the mode of the knower' . And in religion
the mode of the knower differs among the different ways of being human that
are the great cultures of the earth - hence the fact of a number of different
religions. They are different because of their different historical origins
and because they involve different ways of conceiving, and therefore different
ways of experiencing, and therefore different ways of responding in life to
the Transcendent. And not everyone participates in any of them, for a response
to them is not compelled. This is of course a huge topic of which I have only
been able to sketch the outline for our present purpose. There is a great deal
more that can be said but there is no time to say it now.
The kinds of experience I am talking
about are not primarily the seeing of visions and hearing of voices or the dramatically
altered states of consciousness reported by the mystics, but quite common experiences
such as being conscious in prayer, whether in church or elsewhere, of being
in the presence of God, or the experience, in say Buddhist meditation, of being
in a universe which is fundamentally benign and such that there can ultimately
be nothing to fear or to worry about.
So to summarize, we cannot prove that there is an ultimate transcendent reality to which the religions are human, all-too-human responses. But the inner contradiction of physicalism shows that this cannot be ruled out. And whilst those who do not participate at all in the field of religious experience can properly be agnostic about the Transcendent, those of us who do in some degree experience religiously are fully entitled as rational beings to trust that experience and to build our beliefs and our lives on that basis. Religious belief and naturalistic belief are equally faith positions, and each involves risk - in the one case the risk that we are deceiving ourselves, and in the other case the risk that we are being blind to the most important reality of all.
© John Hick, 2002.